Document P6-1: William Graham Sumner, What Social Classes Owe to Each Other (1883)

Social Darwinist Explains Relationship Between Classes

WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, What Social Classes Owe to Each Other (1883)

William Graham Sumner, Yale sociologist and devotee of English philosopher Herbert Spencer, embraced Social Darwinism as a philosophy that structured and framed his understanding of society’s development and progress over time. Inspired by Charles Darwin’s theories of natural selection, Sumner spoke for many latter-nineteenth-century champions of laissez-faire capitalism, who saw the race of life as a struggle that rewarded only those “fittest” to survive. When considering the question of what the social classes owed to one another, the short answer, according to Sumner, was nothing.

“The poor,” “the weak,” “the laborers,” are expressions which are used as if they had exact and well-understood definition. Discussions are made to bear upon the assumed rights, wrongs, and misfortunes of certain social classes; and all public speaking and writing consists, in a large measure, of the discussion of general plans for meeting the wishes of classes of people who have not been able to satisfy their own desires. These classes are sometimes discontented, and sometimes not. Sometimes they do not know that anything is amiss with them until the “friends of humanity” come to them with offers of aid. Sometimes they are discontented and envious. They do not take their achievements as a fair measure of their rights. They do not blame themselves or their parents for their lot, as compared with that of other people. Sometimes they claim that they have a right to everything of which they feel the need for their happiness on earth. To make such a claim against God or Nature would, of course, be only to say that we claim a right to live on earth if we can. But God and Nature have ordained the chances and conditions of life on earth once for all. The case cannot be reopened. We cannot get a revision of the laws of human life. We are absolutely shut up to the need and duty, if we would learn how to live happily, of investigating the laws of Nature, and deducing the rules of right living in the world as it is. These are very wearisome and commonplace tasks. They consist in labor and self-denial repeated over and over again in learning and doing. When the people whose claims we are considering are told to apply themselves to these tasks they become irritated and feel almost insulted. They formulate their claims as rights against society — that is, against some other men. In their view they have a right, not only to pursue happiness, but to get it; and if they fail to get it, they think they have a claim to the aid of other men — that is, to the labor and self-denial of other men — to get it for them. They find orators and poets who tell them that they have grievances, so long as they have unsatisfied desires.

Now, if there are groups of people who have a claim to other people’s labor and self-denial, and if there are other people whose labor and self-denial are liable to be claimed by the first groups, then there certainly are “classes,” and classes of the oldest and most vicious type. For a man who can command another man’s labor and self-denial for the support of his own existence is a privileged person of the highest species conceivable on earth. Princes and paupers meet on this plane, and no other men are on it at all. On the other hand, a man whose labor and self-denial may be diverted from his maintenance to that of some other man is not a free man, and approaches more or less toward the position of a slave. Therefore we shall find that, in all the notions which we are to discuss, this elementary contradiction, that there are classes and that there are not classes, will produce repeated confusion and absurdity. We shall find that, in our efforts to eliminate the old vices of class government, we are impeded and defeated by new products of the worst class theory. We shall find that all the schemes for producing equality and obliterating the organization of society produce a new differentiation based on the worst possible distinction — the right to claim and the duty to give one man’s effort for another man’s satisfaction. We shall find that every effort to realize equality necessitates a sacrifice of liberty.…

The humanitarians, philanthropists, and reformers, looking at the facts of life as they present themselves, find enough which is sad and unpromising in the condition of many members of society. They see wealth and poverty side by side. They note great inequality of social position and social chances. They eagerly set about the attempt to account for what they see, and to devise schemes for remedying what they do not like. In their eagerness to recommend the less fortunate classes to pity and consideration they forget all about the rights of other classes; they gloss over all the faults of the classes in question, and they exaggerate their misfortunes and their virtues. They invent new theories of property, distorting rights and perpetrating injustice, as any one is sure to do who sets about the re-adjustment of social relations with the interests of one group distinctly before his mind, and the interests of all other groups thrown into the background. When I have read certain of these discussions I have thought that it must be quite disreputable to be respectable, quite dishonest to own property, quite unjust to go one’s own way and earn one’s own living, and that the only really admirable person was the good-for-nothing. The man who by his own effort raises himself above poverty appears, in these discussions, to be of no account. The man who has done nothing to raise himself above poverty finds that the social doctors flock about him, bringing the capital which they have collected from the other class, and promising him the aid of the State to give him what the other had to work for. In all these schemes and projects the organized intervention of society through the State is either planned or hoped for, and the State is thus made to become the protector and guardian of certain classes. The agents who are to direct the State action are, of course, the reformers and philanthropists. Their schemes, therefore, may always be reduced to this type — that A and B decide what C shall do for D. It will be interesting to inquire, at a later period of our discussion, who C is, and what the effect is upon him of all these arrangements. In all the discussions attention is concentrated on A and B, the noble social reformers, and on D, the “poor man.” I call C the Forgotten Man, because I have never seen that any notice was taken of him in any of the discussions. When we have disposed of A, B, and D we can better appreciate the case of C, and I think that we shall find that he deserves our attention, for the worth of his character and the magnitude of his unmerited burdens. Here it may suffice to observe that, on the theories of the social philosophers to whom I have referred, we should get a new maxim of judicious living: Poverty is the best policy. If you get wealth, you will have to support other people; if you do not get wealth, it will be the duty of other people to support you.

William Graham Sumner, What Social Classes Owe to Each Other (New York and London: Harper & Brothers Publishers, 1883), 13–16, 21–24.

READING AND DISCUSSION QUESTIONS

  1. Question

    RQA9UjbNv18HmrORTilEMIzZsZKEvUTSc65I4ZWdxKP3JRzpJiuknfjA0yuan9vw9doSAdf7YHnypjC8rfIOA1qTwpOHsqZe+PgOfX2gStRXXOFMF3FyQ5/GcIhIMsN9JgKJd9NLbIqfczuIQlXkrKErMa+6rXxeS0jEizYQ750CiKhwdOGyc/OT5hMCdYVoIgga10SSDzYO8f2Eze+Qn3tYSlY=
  2. Question

    wp8AVRdRzVCCbHnXrtGikt5MefYiWwmvGH32yYY2jEnTAF5mvO6jKNiCO45o8oxnjxsP7OL/SweyHH9qvxE7XATlr8GoTwurl7vK2edFGlwZtErH+9qxoJPs7EsMeNN7dSqo8/0vjKADFlx9HEth+rVbV6Hc7qWmyYilwseVkAHZwLs/UaRcVlqG98OobYALrjVYfyW0IvB3ntWmyhrYO9ZeFKRHlDQKcC1NEyxm3UiyfQdEmQLMLkQkXDYn1WyMf/WGmvHj7ZfPgqyVHLPuvvKZFKldtAu9Eyl6AmhIlbFjA5cIuowoE0RnUEMIZLK8