3. Revolutionary Marxism Defended

3.
Revolutionary Marxism Defended

Vladimir Ilyich Lenin, The State and Revolution (1917)

As World War I dragged on, European governments faced a new foe in civilian protests. The Russian tsar was especially ill equipped for this challenge, which opened the door to revolution. By the fall of 1917, Vladimir Ilyich Lenin (1870–1924) had emerged as the leading voice of Russian revolutionaries thanks in part to his writing. Having spent nearly a decade abroad in exile, he returned to Russia in April 1917 and immediately set to work laying out the blueprint for a one-party proletarian state. As part of this effort, he wrote The State and Revolution several months before he and his Bolshevik Party seized complete control of the government. As he asserts in the excerpt below, the state is indispensable for realizing the promise of a proletarian revolution. To think otherwise, according to Lenin, is to profoundly misunderstand Marx’s and Engels’s vision for social transformation. To persuade his readers of the legitimacy of this vision, Lenin does not simply describe the state as a theoretical entity; he imagines its very existence and argues for its creation. For all of its idealism, however, the government he outlines in this work was far more open than the Soviet state he helped to create.

From Stepan Apresyan and Jim Riordan, trans. and eds., V. I. Lenin: Collected Works, vol. 25, June–September 1917 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1970), 13, 386–87, 396-97, 404, 413, 425–26, 455–56.

What is now happening to Marx’s theory has, in the course of history, happened repeatedly to the theories of revolutionary thinkers and leaders of oppressed classes fighting for emancipation. During the lifetime of great revolutionaries, the oppressing classes constantly hounded them, received their theories with the most savage malice, the most furious hatred, and the most unscrupulous campaigns of lies and slander. After their death, attempts are made to convert them into harmless icons, to canonise them, so to say, and to hallow their names to a certain extent for the “consolation” of the oppressed classes and with the object of duping the latter, while at the same time robbing the revolutionary theory of its substance, blunting its revolutionary edge and vulgarising it. Today, the bourgeoisie and the opportunists within the labour movement concur in this doctoring of Marxism. They omit, obscure, or distort the revolutionary side of this theory, its revolutionary soul. . . .

In these circumstances, in view of the unprecedentedly widespread distortion of Marxism, our prime task is to re-establish what Marx really taught on the subject of the state. . . .

Let us begin with the most popular of Engels’s works, The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State. . . .

Summing up his historical analysis, Engels says:

“The state is, therefore, by no means a power forced on society from without. . . . Rather, it is a product of society at a certain stage of development; it is the admission that this society has become entangled in an insoluble contradiction with itself, that it has split into irreconcilable antagonisms which it is powerless to dispel. . . .

This expresses with perfect clarity the basic idea of Marxism with regard to the historical role and the meaning of the state. The state is a product and a manifestation of the irreconcilability of class antagonisms. The state arises where, when and insofar as class antagonisms objectively cannot be reconciled. And, conversely, the existence of the state proves that the class antagonisms are irreconcilable. . . .

It is safe to say that of this argument of Engels’s, which is so remarkably rich in ideas, only one point has become an integral part of socialist thought among modern socialist parties, namely, that according to Marx the state “withers away”—as distinct from the anarchist doctrine of the “abolition” of the state. To prune Marxism to such an extent means reducing it to opportunism, for this “interpretation” only leaves a vague notion of a slow, even, gradual change, of absence of leaps and storms, of absence of revolution. The current, widespread, popular, if one may say so, conception of the “withering away” of the state undoubtedly means obscuring, if not repudiating, revolution.

Such an “interpretation,” however, is the crudest distortion of Marxism, advantageous only to the bourgeoisie. . . .

In the first place, at the very outset of his argument, Engels says that, in seizing state power, the proletariat thereby “abolishes the state as state.” . . . As a matter of fact, Engels speaks here of the proletarian revolution “abolishing” the bourgeois state, while the words about the state withering away refer to the remnants of the proletarian state after the socialist revolution. According to Engels, the bourgeois state does not “wither away,” but is “abolished” by the proletariat in the course of the revolution. What withers away after this revolution is the proletarian state or semi-state. . . .

The proletariat needs state power, a centralised organisation of force, an organisation of violence, both to crush the resistance of the exploiters and to lead the enormous mass of the population—the peasants, the petty bourgeoisie, and semi-proletarians—in the work of organising a socialist economy.

By educating the workers’ party, Marxism educates the vanguard of the proletariat, capable of assuming power and leading the whole people to socialism, of directing and organising the new system, of being the teacher, the guide, the leader of all the working and exploited people in organising their social life without the bourgeoisie and against the bourgeoisie. By contrast, the opportunism now prevailing trains the members of the workers’ party to be the representatives of the better-paid workers, who lose touch with the masses, “get along” fairly well under capitalism, and sell their birthright for a mess of pottage, i.e., renounce their role as revolutionary leaders of the people against the bourgeoisie.

Marx’s theory of “the state, i.e., the proletariat organised as the ruling class,” is inseparably bound up with the whole of his doctrine of the revolutionary role of the proletariat in history. The culmination of this role is the proletarian dictatorship, the political rule of the proletariat. . . .

The essence of Marx’s theory of the state has been mastered only by those who realise that the dictatorship of a single class is necessary not only for every class society in general, not only for the proletariat which has overthrown the bourgeoisie, but also for the entire historical period which separates capitalism from “classless society,” from communism. Bourgeois states are most varied in form, but their essence is the same: all these states, whatever their form, in the final analysis are inevitably the dictatorship of the bourgeoisie. The transition from capitalism to communism is certainly bound to yield a tremendous abundance and variety of political forms, but the essence will inevitably be the same: the dictatorship of the proletariat. . . .

We are not utopians, we do not “dream” of dispensing at once with all administration, with all subordination. These anarchist dreams, based upon incomprehension of the tasks of the proletarian dictatorship, are totally alien to Marxism, and, as a matter of fact, serve only to postpone the socialist revolution until people are different. No, we want the socialist revolution with people as they are now, with people who cannot dispense with subordination, control, and “foremen and accountants.”

The subordination, however, must be to the armed vanguard of all the exploited and working people, i.e., to the proletariat. A beginning can and must be made at once, overnight, to replace the specific “bossing” of state officials by the simple functions of “foremen and accountants,” functions which are already fully within the ability of the average town dweller and can well be performed for “workmen’s wages.”

We, the workers, shall organise large-scale production on the basis of what capitalism has already created, relying on our own experience as workers, establishing strict, iron discipline backed up by the state power of the armed workers. We shall reduce the role of state officials to that of simply carrying out our instructions as responsible, revocable, modestly paid “foremen and accountants” (of course, with the aid of technicians of all sorts, types and degrees). This is our proletarian task, this is what we can and must start with in accomplishing the proletarian revolution. Such a beginning, on the basis of large-scale production, will of itself lead to the gradual “withering away” of all bureaucracy, to the gradual creation of an order—an order without inverted commas, an order bearing no similarity to wage slavery—an order under which the functions of control and accounting, becoming more and more simple, will be performed by each in turn, will then become a habit and will finally die out as the special functions of a special section of the population. . . .

In the usual arguments about the state, the mistake is constantly made against which Engels warned and which we have in passing indicated above, namely, it is constantly forgotten that the abolition of the state means also the abolition of democracy: that the withering away of the state means the withering away of democracy.

At first sight this assertion seems exceedingly strange and incomprehensible; indeed, someone may even suspect us of expecting the advent of a system of society in which the principle of subordination of the minority to the majority will not be observed—for democracy means the recognition of this very principle.

No, democracy is not identical with the subordination of the minority to the majority. Democracy is a state which recognises the subordination of the minority to the majority, i.e., an organisation for the systematic use of force by one class against another, by one section of the population against another.

We set ourselves the ultimate aim of abolishing the state, i.e., all organised and systematic violence, all use of violence against people in general. We do not expect the advent of a system of society in which the principle of subordination of the minority to the majority will not be observed. In striving for socialism, however, we are convinced that it will develop into communism and, therefore, that the need for violence against people in general, for the subordination of one man to another, and of one section of the population to another, will vanish altogether since people will become accustomed to observing the elementary conditions of social life without violence and without subordination.

DISCUSSION QUESTIONS

  1. What are Lenin’s attitudes toward different classes and social groups? Why are these attitudes important to understanding his vision of the state both before and after the proletarian revolution?

    Question

    nDaGSTB75yMg0WfzDVCtXrCC+08khjzw4Q4sWHO92arIX0aqWl9BuFiGyVJeyVM+YSBDoEqp2RcTeVjT75e78Mb57LEQ0NO9AaCsn6uqoxgxwz02lIqDSq3m5/jwXF2m6bNNvn8C8QfaSG4rWvShhGWbI8srfUj01fQDt3lrkUzuh8ym2O27U3SSDv67N0jltEj/VtXMn058nhajeiZFUjRSnjY2lD6hXaLlrsuQGn0Ll4VLLXDhG0VCQKZu5d6RXN2H4SLXfFguwKqJCb0QoE61FsuyNhTrwSme1s+8BY6F0qHHqI9LbNOBhc2ed2tb
    What are Lenin’s attitudes toward different classes and social groups? Why are these attitudes important to understanding his vision of the state both before and after the proletarian revolution?
  2. Why does the proletariat need state power according to Lenin? Why does he describe this power as a “dictatorship”?

    Question

    9ZsWphTQzCDu7N4Q21DFHKn4aGSEn2mw8fA02v7xrd472T9o2ZOZcwjpN9gLgV74xBsg9E+j6/z51n0tAG7MpoiQ5IZUDMZfEgqlTcVB0/yeXP/ydvIRYl6wD6rRNoSkgGRK2L/pvAfq+VDi6F6b+3wEyo9RMu+l4NHmbW2rjDqqJwFAkOIGZzIOibw/0J7OGJT7MMJwhW6zEuJcjRr8Bg==
    Why does the proletariat need state power according to Lenin? Why does he describe this power as a “dictatorship”?
  3. What role should economics play in this dictatorship? Why is this important to understanding how Lenin’s ideas challenged both the political and economic status quo?

    Question

    PXBcckFt9noz+aAAhrrpy9WK1NmrHgbrS1TkfLNUNMJHF3LTWF0zefHdwW9eC8p0rjHAdzXWuhiS6PuLdFI5wJ1a167QTItbWjUb1/+t5mEXpaGyCptrmgE/Y3Z/KFgIsRSD9HAdGSbKoIuOSSiXIXwLAbI+jo4NGYIY8D53Sps9CPvhsmkf3r0unUjXFi18picU0xOqIgFUZham96LTFNQLU9AcfBZPAxEM4XJtkjGgwKfTQZ00ZzO28Ub5D89HKyVK+y+olHC/+K5QFYgjSlylzIg=
    What role should economics play in this dictatorship? Why is this important to understanding how Lenin’s ideas challenged both the political and economic status quo?