1.3 Module 38: Public Goods and Common Resources

Telekhovskyi/Shutterstock

WHAT YOU WILL LEARN

  • How public goods are characterized and why markets fail to supply efficient quantities of them
  • What common resources are and why they are overused
  • What artificially scarce goods are and why they are underconsumed

In this module, we take a somewhat different approach to the question of why markets sometimes fail. Here we focus on how the characteristics of goods often determine whether markets can deliver them efficiently. When goods have the “wrong” characteristics, the resulting market failures resemble those associated with externalities or market power.

This alternative way of looking at sources of inefficiency deepens our understanding of why markets sometimes don’t work well and how government can take actions that improve the welfare of society.

Private Goods—and Others

What’s the difference between installing a new bathroom in a house and building a municipal sewage system? What’s the difference between growing wheat and fishing in the open ocean?

These aren’t trick questions. In each case there is a basic difference in the characteristics of the goods involved. Bathroom appliances and wheat have the characteristics necessary to allow markets to work efficiently. Public sewage systems and fish in the sea do not.

Let’s look at these crucial characteristics and why they matter.

Characteristics of Goods

Goods like bathroom fixtures and wheat have two characteristics that are essential if a good is to be provided in efficient quantities by a market economy.

A good that is both excludable and rival in consumption is a private good.

When a good is both excludable and rival in consumption, it is called a private good. Wheat is an example of a private good. It is excludable: the farmer can sell a bushel to one consumer without having to provide wheat to everyone in the county. And it is rival in consumption: if I eat bread baked with a farmer’s wheat, that wheat cannot be consumed by someone else.

When a good is nonexcludable, the supplier cannot prevent consumption by people who do not pay for it.

But not all goods possess these two characteristics. Some goods are nonexcludable—​the supplier cannot prevent consumption of the good by people who do not pay for it. Fire protection is one example: a fire department that puts out fires before they spread protects the whole city, not just people who have made contributions to the Firemen’s Benevolent Association. An improved environment is another: pollution can’t be ended for some users of a river while leaving the river foul for others.

A good is nonrival in consumption if more than one person can consume the same unit of the good at the same time.

Nor are all goods rival in consumption. Goods are nonrival in consumption if more than one person can consume the same unit of the good at the same time. TV programs are nonrival in consumption: your decision to watch a show does not prevent other people from watching the same show.

Because goods can be either excludable or nonexcludable, and either rival or nonrival in consumption, there are four types of goods, illustrated by the matrix in Figure 38-1:

There are four types of goods. The type of a good depends on (1) whether or not it is excludable—whether a producer can prevent someone from consuming it; and (2) whether or not it is rival in consumption—whether it is impossible for the same unit of a good to be consumed by more than one person at the same time.

There are, of course, many other characteristics that distinguish between types of goods—necessities versus luxuries, normal versus inferior, and so on. Why focus on whether goods are excludable and rival in consumption?

Why Markets Can Supply Only Private Goods Efficiently

As we learned in earlier modules, markets are typically the best means for a society to deliver goods and services to its members; that is, markets are efficient except in the case of market power, externalities, or other instances of market failure. One source of market failure is rooted in the nature of the good itself: markets cannot supply goods and services efficiently unless they are private goods—excludable and rival in consumption.

To see why excludability is crucial, suppose that a farmer had only two choices: either produce no wheat or provide a bushel of wheat to every resident of the county who wants it, whether or not that resident pays for it. It seems unlikely that anyone would grow wheat under those conditions.

Yet the operator of a public sewage system faces pretty much the same problem as our hypothetical farmer. A sewage system makes the whole city cleaner and healthier—but that benefit accrues to all the city’s residents, whether or not they pay the system operator.

Goods that are nonexcludable suffer from the free-rider problem: individuals have no incentive to pay for their own consumption and instead will take a “free ride” on anyone who does pay.

The general point is that if a good is nonexcludable, rational consumers won’t be willing to pay for it—they will take a “free ride” on anyone who does pay. So there is a free-rider problem. Examples of the free-rider problem are familiar from daily life. One example you may have encountered happens when students are required to do a group project. There is often a tendency of some group members to shirk their responsibilities, relying on others in the group to get the work done. The shirkers free-ride on someone else’s effort.

Because of the free-rider problem, the forces of self-interest alone do not lead to an efficient level of production for a nonexcludable good. Even though consumers would benefit from increased production of the good, no one individual is willing to pay for more, and so no producer is willing to supply it. The result is that nonexcludable goods suffer from inefficiently low production in a market economy. In fact, in the face of the free-rider problem, self-interest may not ensure that any amount of the good—let alone the efficient quantity—​is produced.

When the benefits from a group project are nonexcludable, there is a temptation to free-ride on the efforts of others.
Purestock/Thinkstock

Goods that are excludable and nonrival in consumption, like pay-per-view movies, suffer from a different kind of inefficiency. As long as a good is excludable, it is possible to earn a profit by making it available only to those who pay. Therefore, producers are willing to supply an excludable good. But the marginal cost of letting an additional viewer watch a pay-per-view movie is zero because it is nonrival in consumption. So the efficient price to the consumer is also zero—or, to put it another way, individuals should watch pay-per-view movies up to the point where their marginal benefit is zero.

But if a satellite TV provider actually charges viewers $4, viewers will consume the good only up to the point where their marginal benefit is $4. When consumers must pay a price greater than zero for a good that is nonrival in consumption, the price they pay is higher than the marginal cost of allowing them to consume that good, which is zero. So in a market economy goods that are nonrival in consumption suffer from inefficiently low consumption.

Now we can see why private goods are the only goods that will be produced and consumed in efficient quantities in a competitive market. (That is, a private good will be produced and consumed in efficient quantities in a market free of market power, externalities, and other sources of market failure.) Because private goods are excludable, producers can charge for them and so have an incentive to produce them. And because they are also rival in consumption, it is efficient for consumers to pay a positive price—a price equal to the marginal cost of production. If one or both of these characteristics are lacking, a market economy will lack the incentives to bring about efficient quantities of the good.

Fortunately for the market system, most goods are private goods. Food, clothing, shelter, and most other desirable things in life are excludable and rival in consumption, so markets can provide us with most things. Yet there are crucial goods that don’t meet these criteria—and in most cases, that means that the government must step in.

Public Goods

A public good is both nonexcludable and nonrival in consumption.

A public good is the exact opposite of a private good: it is both nonexcludable and nonrival in consumption. A public sewage system is an example of a public good: you can’t keep a river clean without making it clean for everyone who lives near its banks, and my protection from sewage contamination does not prevent my neighbor from being protected as well.

Here are some other examples of public goods:

Because these goods are nonexcludable, they suffer from the free-rider problem, so private firms would produce inefficiently low quantities of them. And because they are nonrival in consumption, it would be inefficient to charge people for consuming them. As a result, society must find nonmarket methods for providing these goods.

Providing Public Goods

Public goods are provided in a variety of ways. The government doesn’t always get involved—in many cases a nongovernmental solution has been found for the free-rider problem. But these solutions are usually imperfect in some way.

Some public goods are supplied through voluntary contributions. For example, private donations help support public radio and a considerable amount of scientific research. But private donations are insufficient to finance large programs of great importance, such as the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention and national defense.

Some public goods are supplied by self-interested individuals or firms because those who produce them are able to make money in an indirect way. The classic example is broadcast television, which in the United States is supported entirely by advertising. The downside of such indirect funding is that it skews the nature and quantity of the public goods that are supplied, while imposing additional costs on consumers. TV stations show the programs that yield the most advertising revenue (that is, programs best suited for selling antacids, hair-loss remedies, antihistamines, and the like to the segment of the population that buys them), which are not necessarily the programs people most want to see. And viewers must endure many commercials.

Government provides public goods like national defense and the legal system.
Oleg Zabielin/Shutterstock
Rich Legg/Getty Images

Some potentially public goods are deliberately made excludable and therefore subject to charge, like pay-per-view movies. However, as noted earlier, when suppliers charge a price greater than zero for a nonrival good, consumers will consume an inefficiently low quantity of that good.

In small communities, a high level of social encouragement or pressure can be brought to bear on people to contribute money or time to provide the efficient level of a public good. Volunteer fire departments, which depend both on the volunteered services of the firefighters themselves and on contributions from local residents, are a good example. But as communities grow larger and more anonymous, social pressure is increasingly difficult to apply, compelling larger towns and cities to tax residents and depend on salaried firefighters for fire protection services.

As this last example suggests, when other solutions fail, it is up to the government to provide public goods. Indeed, the most important public goods—national defense, the legal system, disease control, fire protection in large cities, and so on—are provided by government and paid for by taxes. Economic theory tells us that the provision of public goods is one of the crucial roles of government.

How Much of a Public Good Should Be Provided?

In some cases, the provision of a public good is an “either–or” decision: a city can either have a sewage system—or not. But in most cases, governments must decide not only whether to provide a public good but also how much of that public good to provide. For example, street cleaning is a public good—but how often should the streets be cleaned? Once a month? Twice a month? Every other day?

Imagine a city with only two residents, Ted and Alice. Assume that the public good in question is street cleaning and that Ted and Alice truthfully tell the government how much they value a unit of the public good, one unit being one street cleaning per month. Specifically, each of them tells the government his or her willingness to pay for another unit of the public good supplied—an amount that corresponds to that individual’s marginal benefit from another unit of the public good.

Using this information along with information on the cost of providing the good, the government can use marginal analysis to find the efficient level of providing the public good: the level at which the marginal social benefit of the public good is equal to the marginal social cost of producing it. Recall that the marginal social benefit of a good is the benefit that accrues to society as a whole from the consumption of one additional unit of the good.

But what is the marginal social benefit of another unit of a public good—a unit that generates utility for all consumers, not just one consumer, because it is nonexcludable and nonrival in consumption?

We all benefit when someone else does the cleaning up.
© a-ts/Alamy

This question leads us to an important principle: In the special case of a public good, the marginal social benefit of a unit of the good is equal to the sum of the individual marginal benefits enjoyed by all consumers of that unit. Or to consider it from a slightly different angle, if a consumer could be compelled to pay for a unit before consuming it (the good is made excludable), then the marginal social benefit of a unit is equal to the sum of each consumer’s willingness to pay for that unit. Using this principle, the marginal social benefit of an additional street cleaning per month is equal to Ted’s individual marginal benefit from that additional cleaning plus Alice’s individual marginal benefit.

Why? Because a public good is nonrival in consumption—Ted’s benefit from a cleaner street does not diminish Alice’s benefit from that same clean street, and vice versa. Because people can simultaneously consume the same unit of street cleaning, the marginal social benefit is the sum of their individual marginal benefits. And the efficient quantity of a public good is the quantity at which the marginal social benefit is equal to the marginal social cost of providing it.

Figure 38-2 illustrates the efficient provision of a public good, showing three marginal benefit curves. Panel (a) shows Ted’s individual marginal benefit curve from street cleaning, MBT: he would be willing to pay $25 for the city to clean its streets once a month, an additional $18 to have it done a second time, and so on. Panel (b) shows Alice’s individual marginal benefit curve from street cleaning, MBA. Panel (c) shows the marginal social benefit curve from street cleaning, MSB: it is the vertical sum of Ted’s and Alice’s individual marginal benefit curves, MBT and MBA.

Panel (a) shows Ted’s individual marginal benefit curve of street cleanings per month, MBT, and panel (b) shows Alice’s individual marginal benefit curve, MBA. Panel (c) shows the marginal social benefit of the public good, equal to the sum of the individual marginal benefits to all consumers (in this case, Ted and Alice). The marginal social benefit curve, MSB, is the vertical sum of the individual marginal benefit curves MBT and MBA. At a constant marginal social cost of $6, there should be 5 street cleanings per month, because the marginal social benefit of going from 4 to 5 cleanings is $8 ($3 for Ted plus $5 for Alice), but the marginal social benefit of going from 5 to 6 cleanings is only $2.

To maximize society’s welfare, the government should increase the quantity of street cleanings until the marginal social benefit of an additional cleaning would fall below the marginal social cost. Suppose that the marginal social cost is $6 per cleaning. Then the city should clean its streets 5 times per month, because the marginal social benefit of each of the first 5 cleanings is more than $6, but going from 5 to 6 cleanings would yield a marginal social benefit of only $2, which is less than the marginal social cost.

One basic rationale for the existence of government is that it provides a way for citizens to tax themselves in order to provide public goods—particularly a vital public good like national defense. Responsible governments try to estimate both the social benefits and the social costs of providing a public good, a process known as cost-benefit analysis.

Of course, if society really consisted of only two individuals, they would probably manage to strike a deal to provide the good. But imagine a city with a million residents, each of whose marginal benefit from a good is only a tiny fraction of the marginal social benefit. It would be impossible for people to reach a voluntary agreement to pay for the efficient level of a good like street cleaning—the potential for free-riding would make it too difficult to make and enforce an agreement among so many people. But they could and would vote to tax themselves to pay for a citywide sanitation department.

VOTING AS A PUBLIC GOOD

It’s a sad fact that many Americans who are eligible to vote don’t bother to. As a result, their interests tend to be ignored by politicians. But what’s even sadder is that this self-defeating behavior may be completely rational.

As the economist Mancur Olson pointed out in a famous book titled The Logic of Collective Action, voting is a public good, one that suffers from severe free-rider problems.

Imagine that you are one of a million people who would stand to gain the equivalent of $100 each if some plan is passed in a statewide referendum—say, a plan to improve public schools. And suppose that the opportunity cost of the time it would take you to vote is $10. Will you be sure to go to the polls and vote for the referendum?

iStockphoto

If you are rational, the answer is no! The reason is that it is very unlikely that your vote will decide the issue, either way. If the measure passes, you benefit, even if you didn’t bother to vote—the benefits are nonexcludable. If the measure doesn’t pass, your vote would not have changed the outcome. Either way, by not voting—by free-riding on those who do vote—you save $10.

Of course, many people do vote out of a sense of civic duty. But because political action is a public good, in general people devote too little effort to defending their own interests.

The result, Olson pointed out, is that when a large group of people share a common political interest, they are likely to exert too little effort promoting their cause and so will be ignored. Conversely, small, well-organized interest groups that act on issues narrowly targeted in their favor tend to have disproportionate power.

Is this a reason to distrust democracy? Winston Churchill said it best: “Democracy is the worst form of government, except for all the other forms that have been tried.”

Common Resources

A common resource is nonexcludable and rival in consumption: you can’t stop me from consuming the good, and more consumption by me means less of the good available for you.

A common resource is a good that is nonexcludable but is rival in consumption. An example is the stock of fish in a fishing area, like the fisheries off the coast of New England. Traditionally, anyone who had a boat could go out to sea and catch fish—fish in the sea were a nonexcludable good. Yet the total number of fish is limited: the fish that one person catches are no longer available to be caught by someone else. So fish in the sea are rival in consumption.

Other examples of common resources include clean air, water, and the diversity of animal and plant species on the planet (biodiversity). In each of these cases the fact that the good is rival in consumption, and yet nonexcludable, poses a serious problem.

The Problem of Overuse

Overuse is the depletion of a common resource that occurs when individuals ignore the fact that their use depletes the amount of the resource remaining for others.

Because common resources are nonexcludable, individuals cannot be charged for their use. But the resources are rival in consumption, so an individual who uses a unit depletes the resource by making that unit unavailable to others. As a result, a common resource is subject to overuse: an individual will continue to use it until his or her marginal benefit is equal to his or her individual marginal cost, ignoring the cost that this action inflicts on society as a whole.

Fish are a classic example of a common resource. Particularly in heavily fished waters, my fishing imposes a cost on others by reducing the fish population and making it harder for others to catch fish. But I have no personal incentive to take this cost into account, since I cannot be charged for fishing. As a result, from society’s point of view, I catch too many fish.

Traffic congestion is another example of overuse of a common resource. A major highway during rush hour can accommodate only a certain number of vehicles per hour. If I decide to drive to work alone rather than carpool or work at home, I cause many other people to have a longer commute; but I have no incentive to take these consequences into account.

In the case of a common resource, the marginal social cost of my use of that resource is higher than my individual marginal cost, the cost to me of using an additional unit of the good. Figure 38-3 illustrates this point. It shows the demand curve for fish, which measures the marginal benefit of fish (as well as the marginal social benefit because there are no external benefits from catching and consuming fish).

The supply curve S, which shows the individual marginal cost of production of the fishing industry, is composed of the individual supply curves of the individual fishermen. But each fisherman’s individual marginal cost does not include the cost that his or her actions impose on others: the depletion of the common resource. As a result, the marginal social cost curve, MSC, lies above the supply curve; in an unregulated market, the quantity of the common resource used, QMKT, exceeds the efficient quantity of use, QOPT.

The figure also shows the supply curve for fish, which measures the marginal cost of production of the fishing industry. We know that the industry supply curve is the horizontal sum of each individual fisherman’s supply curve—equivalent to his or her individual marginal cost curve. The fishing industry supplies the quantity QMKT at which its marginal cost equals the price. But the efficient quantity is QOPT, the quantity of fish that equates the marginal social benefit (as reflected by the demand curve) to the marginal social cost, not to the fishing industry’s marginal cost of production. Thus, the market outcome results in overuse of the common resource.

As we noted, there is a close parallel between the problem of managing a common resource and the problem posed by negative externalities. In the case of an activity that generates a negative externality, the marginal social cost of production is greater than the marginal cost of production, the difference being the marginal external cost imposed on society. Here, the loss to society arising from a fisher’s depletion of the common resource plays the same role as the external cost when there is a negative externality. In fact, many negative externalities (such as pollution) can be thought of as involving common resources (such as clean air).

The Efficient Use and Maintenance of a Common Resource

Because common resources pose problems similar to those created by negative externalities, the solutions are also similar. To ensure efficient use of a common resource, society must find a way to get individual users of the resource to take into account the costs they impose on others. This is the same principle as that of getting individuals to internalize a negative externality that arises from their actions.

There are three principal ways to induce people who use common resources to internalize the costs they impose on others:

  1. Tax or otherwise regulate the use of the common resource
  2. Create a system of tradable licenses for the right to use the common resource
  3. Make the common resource excludable and assign property rights to some individuals
If it weren’t for fees and restrictions, some common resources would be overrun.
iStockphoto/Thinkstock

Tax and RegulateLike activities that generate negative externalities, use of a common resource can be reduced to the efficient quantity by imposing a Pigouvian tax. For example, some countries have imposed “congestion charges” on those who drive during rush hour, in effect charging them for the use of highway space, a common resource. Likewise, visitors to national parks in the United States must pay an entry fee that is essentially a Pigouvian tax.

Create a System of Tradable LicensesAnother way to correct the problem of overuse is to create a system of tradable licenses for the use of the common resource, much like the systems designed to address negative externalities. The policy maker issues the number of licenses that corresponds to the efficient level of use of the good. Making the licenses tradable ensures that the right to use the good is allocated efficiently—that is, those who end up using the good (those willing to pay the most for a license) are those who gain the most from its use.

Assign Property RightsBut when it comes to common resources, often the most natural solution is simply to assign property rights. At a fundamental level, common resources are subject to overuse because nobody owns them. The essence of ownership of a good—the property right over the good—is that you can limit who can and cannot use the good as well as how much of it can be used.

When a good is nonexcludable, in a very real sense no one owns it because a property right cannot be enforced—and consequently no one has an incentive to use it efficiently. So one way to correct the problem of overuse is to make the good excludable and assign property rights over it to someone. The good now has an owner who has an incentive to protect the value of the good—to use it efficiently rather than overuse it. This solution is applicable when currently nonexcludable goods can be made excludable, as with the privatization of parks and even roads, but it cannot be applied to resources that are inherently nonexcludable, including the air and flowing water.

Artificially Scarce Goods

An artificially scarce good is a good that is excludable but nonrival in consumption.

An artificially scarce good is a good that is excludable but nonrival in consumption. As we’ve already seen, pay-per-view movies are a familiar example. The marginal cost to society of allowing an individual to watch a movie is zero because one person’s viewing doesn’t interfere with other people’s viewing. Yet satellite TV providers prevent an individual from seeing a movie if he or she hasn’t paid. Goods like computer software and audio files, which are valued for the information they embody (and are sometimes called information goods), are also artificially scarce.

Markets will supply artificially scarce goods because their excludability allows firms to charge people for them. However, since the efficient price is equal to the marginal cost of zero and the actual price is something higher than that, the good is “artificially scarce” and consumption is inefficiently low. The problem is that, unless the producer can somehow earn revenue from producing and selling the good, none will be produced, which is likely to be worse than a positive but inefficiently low quantity.

We have seen that, in the cases of public goods, common resources, and artificially scarce goods, a market economy will not provide adequate incentives for efficient levels of production and consumption. Fortunately for the sake of market efficiency, most goods are private goods. Food, clothing, shelter, and most other desirable things in life are excludable and rival in consumption, so the types of market failure discussed in this module are important exceptions rather than the norm.

Module 38 Review

Solutions appear at the back of the book.

Check Your Understanding

1. For each of the following goods, indicate whether it is excludable, whether it is rival in consumption, and what kind of good it is.

  • a. a public space such as a park

  • b. a cheese burrito

  • c. information from a website that is password-protected

  • d. publicly announced information about the path of an incoming hurricane

2. Which of the goods in Question 1 will be provided by a private producer without government intervention? Which will not be? Explain your answer.

3. The town of Centreville, population 16, has two types of residents, Homebodies and Revelers. Using the accompanying table, the town must decide how much to spend on its New Year’s Eve party. No individual resident expects to directly bear the cost of the party.

  • a. Suppose there are 10 Homebodies and 6 Revelers. Determine the marginal social benefit schedule of money spent on the party. What is the efficient level of spending?

  • b. Suppose there are 6 Homebodies and 10 Revelers. How do your answers to part a change? Explain.

  • c. Suppose that the individual marginal benefit schedules are known but no one knows the true proportion of Homebodies versus Revelers. Individuals are asked their preferences. What is the likely outcome if each person assumes that others will pay for any additional amount of the public good? Why is it likely to result in an inefficiently high level of spending? Explain.

4. Rocky Mountain Forest is a government-owned forest in which private citizens were allowed in the past to harvest as much timber as they wanted free of charge. State in economic terms why this is problematic from society’s point of view.

5. You are the new Forest Service Commissioner and have been instructed to come up with ways to preserve the Rocky Mountain Forest for the general public. Name three different methods you could use to maintain the efficient level of tree harvesting and explain how each would work. For each method, what information would you need to know in order to achieve an efficient outcome?

Multiple-Choice Questions

Question

EaH0L+jZBYhhLdS950jQaBF+XNNX+BRczQ0DUqiajoIzTG3NSDUGlsh0Tnk3oPVeTbPZgiQhzSJKsvbPxn0BuP+6aAbjDc8JSO4EzmEftmHuRj/3RY+JxuywCW05aSRmB1kW5whEbRrK+MPLJpdgM4VAlKl7/3XD+rarIPAE7imncoBcA1TM6oMaUQHYXCiHWy0gbLV2Nmkx7+kcH6NL1QauOlC6GBMDzphIepHWDQx//Ctg61dLDM+TUx5JCXqYppDXSnLFt71SX/BZ4Qa9u0o8DTYUNlarw9wShzNAJOhhcTx91Y3/pAKWzDgvvtzcQ5M5gxO1tPFh65eG2iqtAw==

Question

p1pGy0nXDSS8iZOt58GHF5RnyJir2drzPFuP5bXK1fm65O/aes7FKaGtRbMlfOp21Gb/pOVy/DZ4c/BoKeG8vv6BNiRg6CSaTJ3Y08D0T9s0gLGaX0OVe6vNXL1RVn28DciXCUUl+/VUr7hSSYgvc5sqBJ/0QVPmwl+hNowI+ubLKLHCba0ED1l1Jv5pvaJgEXaOQgBU6FIHRmyHGxOJkJnVKQ63QxHP72vTYRt8t2zRgyru7/WhlZx0GBQhU6u5HJEfJ0CUi3LtqGQJyaBsXZXq411gOaYH6EnuDbebHcXexMjFmWD/8e67AnZ13N5Kv2E9Hs9NxMdM1Q24Y/Qpm6BsBM+7aNvD9Er7wahZYZQ=

Question

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

Question

/pcjK84woWHUFgBBqxOG9JuOxYeIY+QuFPYaUvzDyUpLNyCEHr6Ane7PshN6HL/5M/gWYVKWIVIILlM+21riLNWCQYRQUAMry4AGGtCblH1eT6d2TVqTc23WWvZDPD96UtApuUd/scNcSX4FyiegUkuWTw9Y3qSHbNTNcMVua/uAbqsXkJpBOjIX1/bKHS/sa4dPArhCscjzQUAkrz128bG3+TINUABhdjeriv6R40X+1l03FYBplm4Wpdr7dVC4Oqel33BuPIEunGUZYVO7guIS70zv6mxarNRjAbIj1UGcxcTyiLydN300Ib0TLLq+hPcMLYDPIkw2U1nLM1VA88x/YwKLPL/sUC2GbtHG4uATObLE/2m6zTq1KOyxfT47zhSItwd9icVcePFh

Question

2IJZvC7IhCSzo2VGctMDygSCEE4FR+c+C4FM5kbRQPHRS2Yncyt8CLmokHGKBT0AZv28QnUqJz+qvZWqRKCeitXFcZtzyXbMssJAZpsZalSw/V3XGMY3qTXtwtOqewE9k23rSN7nVHeB9wD6n7MYzJc3UCL8WPlYSG7q25mMiWXCIDyxJB7uYngJ8W325josGuVz14wOSZZFmCr+LPCq0GGpb1atnl++3L31e22nCRQLn0g/TwObufYkH17+rH2PhvVdmNvT2le/h+BZO0FGvuq2YZJpNBf2tiR5mMO9QhYF08iD8xv2y6wmhHmn0m1e5j+LzWNQpXmbWFfJ8PEgWDwHoRFW7uUhWL8AErXoZCo=

Critical-Thinking Questions

1. Identify and explain the two characteristics shared by every public good.

2. Suppose a new resident moves to a community that purchases a public good for the benefit of every member of the community. What is the additional cost of providing the public good to the new community member? Explain.

PITFALLS: THE MARGINAL COST OF WHAT EXACTLY?

THE MARGINAL COST OF WHAT EXACTLY?

When we consider the marginal cost of a good that is nonrival in consumption, what exactly are we thinking about? What about a good that is rival in consumption?

In the case of a good that is nonrival in consumption, we could consider either the marginal cost of producing a unit of the good or the marginal cost of allowing a unit of the good to be consumed. It is easy to confuse the two, but try not to. To help clarify the distinction, consider this example: the satellite TV provider DirecTV incurs a marginal cost in making a movie available to its subscribers that is equal to the cost of the resources it uses to produce and broadcast that movie. However, once that movie is being broadcast, no marginal cost is incurred by letting an additional family watch it. In other words, no costly resources are “used up” when one more family consumes a movie that has already been produced and is being broadcast.

This complication does not arise, however, when a good is rival in consumption. In this case, the resources used to produce a unit of the good are “used up” by a person’s consumption of it—they are no longer available to satisfy someone else’s consumption. So when a good is rival in consumption, the marginal cost to society of allowing an individual to consume a unit is equal to the resource cost of producing that unit—that is, equal to the marginal cost of producing it.