165
This article originally appeared on TheDailyBeast.com on January 1, 2014.
SHOULD NEO-
THANE ROSENBAUM
1
Over the past several weeks, free speech has gotten costlier—
2
In France, Dieudonne M’Bala M’Bala, an anti-
3
Meanwhile, Israel’s parliament is soon to pass a bill outlawing the word Nazi for non-
4
To Americans, these actions in France and Israel seem positively un-
5
While what is happening in France and Israel is wholly foreign to Americans, perhaps it’s time to consider whether these and other countries may be right. Perhaps America’s fixation on free speech has gone too far.
6
Actually, the United States is an outlier among democracies in granting such generous free speech guarantees. Six European countries, along with Brazil, prohibit the use of Nazi symbols and flags. Many more countries have outlawed Holocaust denial. Indeed, even encouraging racial discrimination in France is a crime. In pluralistic nations like these with clashing cultures and historical tragedies not shared by all, mutual respect and civility helps keep the peace and avoids unnecessary mental trauma.
7
Yet, even in the United States, free speech is not unlimited. Certain proscribed categories have always existed—
166
8
Yet, the confusion is that in placing limits on speech we privilege physical over emotional harm. Indeed, we have an entire legal system, and an attitude toward speech, that takes its cue from a nursery rhyme: “Sticks and stones can break my bones but names can never hurt me.”
9
All of us know, however, and despite what we tell our children, names do, indeed, hurt. And recent studies in universities such as Purdue, UCLA, Michigan, Toronto, Arizona, Maryland, and Macquarie University in New South Wales show, among other things, through brain scans and controlled studies with participants who were subjected to both physical and emotional pain, that emotional harm is equal in intensity to that experienced by the body, and is even more long-
10
Pain has a shared circuitry in the human brain, and it makes no distinction between being hit in the face and losing face (or having a broken heart) as a result of bereavement, betrayal, social exclusion, and grave insult. Emotional distress can, in fact, make the body sick. Indeed, research has shown that pain relief medication can work equally well for both physical and emotional injury.
11
“We impose speed limits on driving and regulate food and drugs because we know that the costs of not doing so can lead to accidents and harm.”
We impose speed limits on driving and regulate food and drugs because we know that the costs of not doing so can lead to accidents and harm. Why should speech be exempt from public welfare concerns when its social costs can be even more injurious?
12
In the marketplace of ideas, there is a difference between trying to persuade and trying to injure. One can object to gays in the military without ruining the one moment a father has to bury his son; neo-
13
Of course, everything is a matter of degree. Juries are faced with similar ambiguities when it comes to physical injury. No one knows for certain whether the plaintiff wearing a neck brace can’t actually run the New York Marathon. We tolerate the fake slip and fall, but we feel absolutely helpless in evaluating whether words and gestures intended to harm actually do cause harm. Jurors are as capable of working through these uncertainties in the area of emotional harms as they are in the realm of physical injury.
14
Free speech should not stand in the way of common decency. No right should be so freely and recklessly exercised that it becomes an impediment to civil society, making it so that others are made to feel less free, their private space and peace invaded, their sensitivities cruelly trampled upon.
167
AT ISSUE: HOW FREE SHOULD FREE SPEECH BE?
Rosenbaum waits until the end of paragraph 6 to state his thesis. Why? What information does he include in paragraphs 1–
Rosenbaum develops his argument with both inductive and deductive reasoning. Where does he use each strategy?
What evidence does Rosenbaum use to support his thesis? Should he have included more evidence? If so, what kind?
In paragraph 11, Rosenbaum makes a comparison between regulating free speech and regulating driving and food and drugs. How strong is this analogy? At what points (if any) does this comparison break down?
Where does Rosenbaum address arguments against his position? Does he refute these arguments? What other opposing arguments could he have addressed?
What point does Rosenbaum reinforce in his conclusion? What other points could he have emphasized?