Primary Source 23.3: Ernest Renan on National Identity

In a lecture delivered at the University of Paris in 1882, excerpted here, French philosopher Ernest Renan claimed that Western society was far too heterogeneous for nationhood to be based simply on a common language, religion, or geographic territory. He asserted that the notion of a pure national “race” — an idea particularly popular in Germany — was “a complete illusion.” Instead, Renan argued that national identity depended on an imagined past and future that had less to do with historical reality than with current aspirations for an idealized sense of collective belonging.

image A nation is a soul, a spiritual principle. Two things, which in truth are but one, constitute this soul or spiritual principle. One lies in the past, one in the present. One is the possession in common of a rich legacy of memories; the other is present-day consent, the desire to live together, the will to perpetuate the value of the heritage that one has received in an undivided form…. The nation, like the individual, is the culmination of a long past of endeavours, sacrifice, and devotion. Of all cults, that of the ancestors is the most legitimate, for the ancestors have made us what we are. A heroic past, great men, glory … this is the social capital upon which one bases a national idea. To have common glories in the past and to have a common will in the present; to have performed great deeds together, to wish to perform still more — these are the essential conditions for being a people….

More valuable by far than common customs posts and frontiers conforming to strategic ideas is the fact of sharing, in the past, a glorious heritage and regrets, and of having, in the future, [a shared] programme to put into effect, or the fact of having suffered, enjoyed, and hoped together. These are the kinds of things that can be understood in spite of differences of race and language. I spoke just now of “having suffered together” and, indeed, suffering in common unifies more than joy does. Where national memories are concerned, griefs are of more value than triumphs, for they impose duties, and require a common effort.

A nation is therefore a large-scale solidarity, constituted by the feeling of the sacrifices that one has made in the past and of those that one is prepared to make in the future. It presupposes a past; it is summarized, however, in the present by a tangible fact, namely, consent, the clearly expressed desire to continue a common life. A nation’s existence is, if you will pardon the metaphor, a daily plebiscite, just as an individual’s existence is a perpetual affirmation of life…. A nation has no more right than a king does to say to a province: “You belong to me, I am seizing you.” A province, as far as I am concerned, is its inhabitants; if anyone has the right to be consulted in such an affair, it is the inhabitant. A nation never has any real interest in annexing or holding on to a country against its will. The wish of nations is, all in all, the sole legitimate criterion, the one to which one must always return. image

Source: Ernest Renan, “What Is a Nation?” trans. Martin Thom, in Nation and Narration, ed. Homi K. Bhabha (New York: Routledge, 2003), pp. 19–20. Reprinted by permission of Taylor and Francis Books.

EVALUATE THE EVIDENCE

  1. Question

    IvoxpqFHVRxW8dYYclWoo8pgm9r/VUs9wSJabDxrOtVoKSu5tbJv7loMxuT/yt6ENepsSMK28/n6jpbk60WbYgsPMjkB67bZYYDrejjJr1vdx+TORF77fowvekUnb085nbFMAw==
  2. Question

    o2QWHBnTJBzzD+VPv+Z0RWw+lsynGe5RQtlQfpgLzS7tVJXi6ONFKquW5OUDGdpflFi9+S0vwQJuYhMFkwHZq6HxsEOoLoXyBs83lqxaiGl0KoYvnU7muquMti4XVQp/