The Methods of Science: Bacon and Descartes

514

One of the keys to the achievement of a new worldview in the seventeenth century was the development of better ways of obtaining knowledge. Two important thinkers, Francis Bacon (1561–1626) and René Descartes (day-KAHRT) (1596–1650), were influential in describing and advocating for improved scientific methods based, respectively, on experimentation and mathematical reasoning.

The English politician and writer Francis Bacon was the greatest early propagandist for the experimental method. Rejecting the Aristotelian and medieval method of using speculative reasoning to build general theories, Bacon argued that new knowledge had to be pursued through empirical research. The researcher who wants to learn more about leaves or rocks, for example, should not speculate about the subject but rather collect a multitude of specimens and then compare and analyze them to derive general principles. Bacon formalized the empirical method, which had already been used by Brahe and Galileo, into the general theory of inductive reasoning known as empiricism. Bacon’s work, and his prestige as lord chancellor under James I, led to the widespread adoption of what was called “experimental philosophy” in England after his death. In 1660 followers of Bacon created the Royal Society (still in existence), which met weekly to conduct experiments and discuss the latest findings of scholars across Europe.

515

On the continent, more speculative methods retained support. In 1619, as a twenty-three-year-old soldier serving in the Thirty Years’ War, the French philosopher René Descartes experienced a life-changing intellectual vision. Descartes saw that there was a perfect correspondence between geometry and algebra and that geometrical spatial figures could be expressed as algebraic equations and vice versa. A major step forward in the history of mathematics, Descartes’s discovery of analytic geometry provided scientists with an important new tool.

Descartes used mathematics to elaborate a highly influential vision of the workings of the cosmos. Accepting Galileo’s claim that all elements of the universe are composed of the same matter, Descartes began to investigate the basic nature of matter. Drawing on ancient Greek atomist philosophies, Descartes developed the idea that matter was made up of identical “corpuscles” (tiny particles) that collided together in an endless series of motions, akin to the workings of a machine. All occurrences in nature could be analyzed as matter in motion and, according to Descartes, the total “quantity of motion” in the universe was constant. Descartes’s mechanistic view of the universe depended on the idea that a vacuum was impossible, which meant that every action had an equal reaction, continuing in an eternal chain reaction.

Although Descartes’s hypothesis about the vacuum was proved wrong, his notion of a mechanistic universe intelligible through the physics of motion proved inspirational. Decades later, Newton rejected Descartes’s idea of a full universe and several of his other ideas, but retained the notion of a mechanistic universe as a key element of his own system.

Descartes’s greatest achievement was to develop his initial vision into a whole philosophy of knowledge and science. The Aristotelian cosmos was appealing in part because it corresponded with the evidence of the human senses. When experiments proved that sensory impressions could be wrong, Descartes decided it was necessary to doubt them and everything that could reasonably be doubted, and to then, as in geometry, use deductive reasoning from self-evident truths, which he called “first principles,” to ascertain scientific laws. Descartes’s reasoning ultimately reduced all substances to “matter” and “mind” — that is, to the physical and the spiritual. The devout Descartes believed that God had endowed man with reason for a purpose and that rational speculation could provide a path to the truths of creation. His view of the world as consisting of two fundamental entities is known as Cartesian dualism. Descartes’s thought was highly influential in France and the Netherlands, but less so in England, where experimental philosophy won the day.

Major Contributors to the Scientific Revolution

Nicolaus Copernicus (1473–1543) On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres (1543); theorized that the sun, rather than the earth, was the center of the galaxy
Paracelsus (1493–1541) Swiss physician and alchemist who pioneered the use of chemicals and drugs to address illness
Andreas Vesalius (1514–1564) On the Structure of the Human Body (1543)
Tycho Brahe (1546–1601) Built observatory and compiled data for the Rudolphine Tables, a new table of planetary data
Francis Bacon (1561–1626) Advocated experimental method, formalizing theory of inductive reasoning known as empiricism
Galileo Galilei (1564–1642) Used telescopic observation to provide evidence for Copernican hypothesis; experimented to formulate laws of physics, such as inertia
Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) Used Brahe’s data to mathematically prove the Copernican hypothesis; his new laws of planetary motion united for the first time natural philosophy and mathematics; completed the Rudolphine Tables in 1627
William Harvey (1578–1657) Discovery of circulation of blood (1628)
René Descartes (1596–1650) Used deductive reasoning to formulate the theory of Cartesian dualism
Robert Boyle (1627–1691) Boyle’s law (1662) governing the pressure of gases
Isaac Newton (1642–1727) Principia Mathematica (1687); set forth the law of universal gravitation, synthesizing previous findings of motion and matter

Both Bacon’s inductive experimentalism and Descartes’s deductive mathematical reasoning had flaws. Bacon’s inability to appreciate the importance of mathematics and his obsession with practical results clearly showed the limitations of antitheoretical empiricism. Likewise, some of Descartes’s positions demonstrated the inadequacy of rigid, dogmatic rationalism. For example, he believed that it was possible to deduce the whole science of medicine from first principles. Although insufficient on their own, Bacon’s and Descartes’s extreme approaches are combined in the modern scientific method, which began to crystallize in the late seventeenth century.